Catéchisme des Industriels (1823)
Q. What developments took place in industry from Louis 11 up to and
including the reign of Louis 14? What caused this advance and the
importance acquired by the industrials?
A. By the fifteenth century the monarchy had already acquired a great deal
of strength compared with its position at the time of the conquest of the
Gauls by the Franks, when it was merely the generalship of the Frankish
army, nominated by the chieftains whose troops made up this army.
When Louis 14 ascended the throne he recognised that the monarchy was still
only a very precarious institution with no positive and stable character.
He recognised that the sovereign power still belonged collectively to the
barons, that the King was in reality only the most important baron, and
that those barons descended from chieftains still subscribed to the
tradition that the King was a primus inter pares, to be appointed
and dismissed according to their wishes. He recognised, finally, the need
to fix his attention on the fact that in France the barons were
collectively stronger and more powerful than the King, and that under the
feudal constitution the monarchy could maintain its supremacy only by
keeping the barons divided and attracting some of the most powerful barons
to its side.
Louis 14 conceived the bold plan of concentrating all sovereign power in
the hands of the monarchy, destroying the supremacy of the Franks over the
Gauls, destroying the feudal system, abolishing the institutions of
nobility, and making himself King of the Gauls instead of chief of the
Franks.
If this plan was to be successful, the King had to merge his authority with
the interests of a class strong enough to support him and ensure the
success of his enterprise. He united with the industrials.
The industrials wanted the sovereign power to be concentrated in the hands
of the monarchy, because this was the only way of destroying the
impediments to commerce in France, which resulted from the division of the
sovereign power. They also wanted to become the first class in society, as
much to satisfy their self-esteem as to achieve the material advantages
involved in making the law (the law always favouring its makers).
Consequently, the industrials accepted the alliance proposed by the
monarchy, an alliance which they have maintained ever since.
Louis 11 may thus be regarded as the founder of the league formed in the
fifteenth century between the monarchy and industry against the nobility,
between the King of France and the Gauls against the descendants of the
Franks.
The struggle between the king and the great vassals, between the chiefs of
industrial enterprises and the nobles, lasted for more than two hundred
years before the sovereign powers were concentrated in the hands of the
monarchy, and before the direction of industrial enterprises by the nobles
had completely ceased. But in the end Louis 14 saw the descendants or
successors of the most important chieftains (who had subsequently become
barons) fill his antechambers in their efforts to obtain household posts.
And at last the numerous class of workingmen had no other leaders, in their
work, but men drawn from their ranks and whose capacity or wealth had
enabled them to become entrepreneurs of some industrial enterprise.
GUSTAVE D'EICHTHAL to J.S.MILL
Quoted
Manuel, F.E. 1963
p.421
23.11.1829 letter said that for two years none of the disciples was able to
grasp the full meaning of Nouveau Christianisme.
1.12.1829
"
The religious doctrine of Saint-Simon has this unitary
character which should gather about it all the men of the future. It puts
neither spirit above matter, nor matter above
spirit. It considers them as intimately united one with the other,
as being the condition one of the other, as being the two modes in which
being is manifest, living being, sympathetic being."
"Saint-Simon, after having in his early writings tried to reorganise
society in the name of Science, after having later renewed the same attempt
in the name of Industry, realized that he had mistaken the means for
the end; that it is in the name of their sympathies that one
must speak to men, and above all, in the name of their religious
sympathies which should summarize all others."
Quotes from
"The Spirit of the Age", by
John Stuart Mill, a series of
articles in The Examiner 6.1.1831 to 29.5.1831.
The Examiner 9.1.1831.
MillCW22 p.228:
The "Spirit of the Age" is in some measure a novel expression. I do not
believe it is to be met in any work exceeding fifty years in antiquity. The
idea of comparing one's own age with former ages, or with our notion of
those which are yet to come, had occurred to philosophers, but it never
before was itself the dominant idea of any age.
etc
The conviction is already not far from being universal, that the times are
pregnant with change; and that the nineteenth century will be known to
posterity as the era of one of the greatest revolutions of which history
has preserved the remembrance, in the
human mind, and in
the whole constitution of human society.
The first of the leading peculiarities of the present age is that it is
an age of transition. Mankind have outgrown old institutions and old
doctrines, and have not yet acquired new ones. When we say outgrown, we
intend to prejudge nothing. A man may not be either better or happier at
six-and-twenty, than he was at six years of age: but the same jacket which
fitted him then, will not fit him now.
The Examiner 23.1.1831
MillCW22 p.238:
I have said that the present age is an age of transition. I shall now
attempt to point out one of the most important consequences of this fact.
In all other conditions of mankind, the uninstructed have faith in the
instructed. in an age of transition, the divisions among the instructed
nullify their authority, and the uninstructed lose their faith in them. The
multitude are without a guide
; and society is exposed to all the errors and dangers which are to be
expected when persons who have never studied any branch of knowledge
comprehensively and as a whole attempt to judge for themselves upon
particular parts of it.
The Examiner 6.2.1831.
Mill, J.S. 1976 p.176,
MillCW22 p.252
The affairs of mankind, or of any of those smaller political societies
which we call nations, are always either in one or the other of two states,
one of them in its nature durable, the other essentially transitory. The
former of these we may term the natural state, the latter the
transitional.
Society may be said to be in its natural state, when worldly power, and
moral influence, are habitually and undisputedly exercised by the fittest
persons whom the existing state of society affords. Or, to be more
explicit; when on the one hand, the temporal, or, as the French would say,
the material [p.177] interests of the community, are managed by
those of its members who possess the greatest capacity for such management;
and on the other hand, those whose opinions the people follow, whose
feelings they imbibe, and who practically and by common consent, perform,
no matter under what original title, the office of thinking for the people,
are persons better qualified than any others whom the civilization of the
age and country affords to think and judge rightly and usefully.
The Examiner 13.3.1831
MillCW22 p.278:
It is not necessary for me to point out that until a comparatively
recent period, none but the wealthy, and even, i might say, the hereditary
wealthy, had it in their power to acquire the intelligence, the knowledge,
and the habits, which are necessary to qualify a man, in any tolerable
degree, for managing the affairs of his country.
The Examiner 3.4.1831
MillCW22 p.289
It has been stated, in the preceding paper, that the conditions which
confer worldly power are still, amidst all changes of circumstances, the
same as in the middle ages - namely, the possession of wealth, or the being
employed and trusted by the wealthy.
The Examiner 15.5.1831
MillCW22 p.304:
In commencing this series of papers, I intended, and attempted, that
the divisions of my discourse should correspond with those of my subject,
and that each number should comprehend within its own limits all which was
necessary to the expansion and illustration of one single idea. The nature
of the publication, which, as being read by more persons capable of
understanding the drift of such speculations (and by fewer, in proportion,
who are unfit for them) than any other single work, I considered myself
fortunate in being able to adopt as a vehicle for my ideas, compels me to
limit the length of each article more than is compatible with my original
plan. I can no longer always hope that every paper should be complete
within itself; and the present number, had it appeared in its proper place,
would have formed the continuation of the last.
The Examiner 29.5.1831
MillCW22 p.312:
In the countries that remained Catholic, but where the Catholic
hierarchy did not retain sufficient moral ascendancy to succeed in stopping
the progress of civilisation, the church was compelled, by the decline of
its separate influence, to link itself more and more closely with the
temporal sovereignty. And thus did it retard its own downfall, until the
spirit of the age became too strong for the two united, and both fell
together to the ground.
AUGUSTE COMTE, 1798-1857
Disciple of Saint-Simon from 1818-1824. Author of Cours de Philosophie
Positive (6 volumes), published 1830-1842; translated into English
1853. Word Sociology first coined in volume four (1838).
Born Montpellier, 19.1.1798. From about the age of 20 (1818?) he taught
mathematics in Paris. As a result of his association with Saint-Simon he
also wrote philosophical articles for journals. At about 28 (1826?) he
began a series of philosophical lectures which attracted considerable
attention; but after the third of these, he attempted suicide. Two years
later he was well enough to resume his lectures. He maintained himself by
teaching and examining mathematics. Lawsuits, however, resulted in his
losing a great part of his income. John Stuart Mill (who never met Comte),
raised money to support him. When this could not be renewed, Comte broke of
relations with Mill. An appeal was made on his behalf by influential men in
France, which resulted in a small income, sufficient to live on, for the
rest of his life. In 1848 Comte founded the Positivist Society. From 1849
to 1851 he lectured on his philosophy at the Palais Royal.
J.S. Mill's description of Comte's Positivism
"The fundamental doctrine of a true philosophy, according to M.
Comte, and the character by which he defines Positive Philosophy, is the
following:
"- We have no knowledge of anything but Phenomena; and our knowledge
of
phenomena is relative, not absolute. We know not the essence, nor the
real mode of production, of any fact, but only its relation to other
facts in the way of succession or of similitude. These relations are
constant; that is, always the same in the same circumstances. The
constant resemblances which link phenomena together, and the constant
sequences which unite them as antecedent and consequent, are termed
their laws. The laws of phenomena are all we know respecting them.
Their essential nature, and their ultimate causes, either efficient
or final, are unknown and inscrutable to us."
(Mill, J.S.
1865/Comte/1969 pp 265-266)
Comte extracts -
Cours de Philosophic Positive (Synoptic Table) -
1853 Condensed (English)
version